Bruno Latour
Ecole des Mines, Paris
Published originally in Karin Knorr-Cetina
and Michael Mulkay, eds., Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social
Study of Science, London and Beverly Hills; Sage, 1983, pp. 141-170.
(pagination of the original text is preserved in the present version.)
Now that feld studies of laboratory
practices are starting to pour in, we are beginning to have a better picture
of what scientists do inside the walls of these strange places called 'laboratories'
(KnorrCetina, this volume). But a new problem has emerged. If we are
not able to follow up our participantobservation studies far enough
to take in questions outside the laboratory, we are at great risk of falling
back into the socalled 'internalist' vision of science. From the very beginnings
of these microstudies, this criticism was levelled at us by scholars preoccupied
by larger problems such as science policy, history of science, or more
broadly, what is known as Science, Technology and Society (STS). For such
topics, laboratory studies seemed utterly irrelevant. At the time, our
critics were largely wrong because we first of all had to penetrate these
black boxes, and to get firsthand observations of the daily activity of
scientists. This was the foremost priority. The result, to summarize it
in one sentence, was that nothing extraordinary and nothing 'scientific'
was happening inside the sacred walls of these temples (Knorr, 1981). After
a few years of studies, however, our critics would be right in raising
again the naive but nagging question: if nothing scientific is happening
in laboratories, why are there laboratories to begin with and
Author's note: Many arguments
developed here are commentaries on ideas discussed with my colleague Michel
Callon. I wish to thank Mark Smith for his assistance in preparing the
manuscript.
142
Bruno Latour
why, strangely enough, is the society
surrounding them paying for these places where nothing special is produced?
The question appears innocent enough,
but is actually a rather tricky one because there is a division of labour
between scholars studying organizations, institutions, public policy on
the one hand, and people studying micronegotiations inside scientific disciplines
on the other. It is truly difficult to see common elements between the
analysis of the laetrile controversy (Nelkin, 1979) and the semiotic study
of a single scientific text (Bastide, 1981); between the study of indicators
for following the growth of R&D and the history of the gravitational
wave detector (Collins, 1975); or between the Windscale Inquiry and the
deciphering of the mutterings of a few scientists during a chat at a bench
(Lynch, 1982); it is so hard to grasp common features among these interests,
that people tend to think that there are indeed 'macroscopic' problems,
and that the two sets of issues ought to be treated differently, with different
methods, by different breeds of scholars. This belief in a real difference
of scale between macro and microobjects in society is common
among sociologists (Knorr and Cicourel, 1981), but is especially strong
in sociology of science. Many analysts of STS are proud of not entering
at all into the content of science and into the microlevel of scientific
negotiations, while, at the other end of the spectrum, some analysts claim
that they are interested only in controversies between scientists (Collins,
1982), or even claim that there is no society at all or at least no macrosociety
about which something serious could be uttered (Woolgar, 1981). The funny
thing about this misunderstanding is that it reproduces on slightly different
grounds the ageold polemic between 'internalist' and 'externalist'
in the study of science and technology. While the debates of earlier times
opposed 'social influences' to 'purely internal development' in accounting
for the movement of scientific disciplines, people are now opposing 'public
policy', 'largescale economic push and pull' to 'micronegotiations',
'opportunism' and 'laboratory folklore'. The terms have changed, the belief
in the 'scientificity' of science has disappeared, but the same respect
for the boundaries of scientific activity is manifested by both schools
of thought.
The time has now come for the analysts
of scientists at work to deal with the na~ve but fair criticism put to
them by scholars interested in 'macro' issues. But there is of course no
way that we can easily conciliate such profoundly different perspectives
and methods. In particular, it is impossible for observers used to laboratory
studies to leave this firm ground where so much has been achieved and simply
dive into 'macro'
Give me a laboratory...
143
problems, computing gross national
product percentages, citations and rewards and so on. If we do deal with
these questions it will be on our own terms.
In this chapter, I would like to propose
a simple line of enquiry: that is, to stick with the methodology developed
during laboratory field studies, focusing it not on the laboratory itself
but on the construction of the laboratory and its position in the societal
milieu (Callon, 1982). Indeed, I hope to convince the reader that the very
difference between the 'inside' and the 'outside', and the difference of
scale between 'micro' and 'macro' levels, is precisely what laboratories
are built to destabilize or undo. So much so, that without keeping back
the discoveries we made while studying laboratory practices we can reassess
the socalled 'macro' problems much more clearly than before and even
throw some light on the very construction of macroactors themselves. I
simply beg the readers to put aside for a time their belief in any real
difference between micro and macroactors at least for the reading
of this paper (Callon and Latour, 1981).
I. 'Give me a place to stand
and I will move the earth'
To illustrate my argument I will extract
an example from a recent study done in the history of science (Latour,
1981a). We are in the year 1881, the French semipopular and scientific
press is full of articles about the work being done in a certain laboratory,
that of Monsieur Pasteur at the (core Normale Superieure. Day after day,
week after week, journalists, fellow scientists, physicians and hygienists
focus their attention on what is happening to a few colonies of microbes
in different mediums, under the microscope, inside inoculated animals,
in the hands of a few scientists. The mere existence of this enormous interest
shows the irrelevance of too sharp a distinction between the 'inside' and
the 'outside' of Pasteur's lab. What is relevant is the short circuit established
between many groups usually uninterested by what happens inside laboratory
walls, and laboratories usually isolated and insulated from such attention
and passion. Somehow, something is happening in these dishes that seems
directly essential to the projects of these many groups expressing their
concern in the joumals.
This interest of outsiders for lab
experiments is not a given: it is the result of Pasteur's work in enrolling
and enlisting them. This is worth emphasizing since there is a quarrel
among sociologists of science about the possibility of imputing interests
to people. Some, especially the
144
Bruno Latour
Edinburgh school, claim that we can
impute interests to social groups given a general idea of what the groups
are, what society is made of, and even what the nature of man is like.
But others (Woolgar, 1981) deny the possibility of such imputation on the
grounds that we do not have any independent way of knowing what the groups
are, what society is after and what the nature of man is like. This dispute,
like most, misses the fundamental point. Of course there is no way of knowing
which are the groups, what they want and what man is, but this does not
stop anyone from convincing others of what their interests are and what
they ought to want and to be. He who is able to translate others' interests
into his own language carries the day. It is especially important not to
rely on any science of society or science of man to impute interests because
as I will show, sciences are one of the most convincing tools to persuade
others of who they are and what they should want. A sociology of science
is crippled from the start if it believes in the results of one science,
namely sociology, to explain the others. But it is still possible to follow
how sciences are used to transform society and redefine what it is made
of and what are its aims. So it is useless to look for the profit that
people can reap from being interested in Pasteur's laboratory. Their interests
are a consequence and not a cause of Pasteur's efforts to translate what
they want or what he makes them want. They have no a priori reason to be
interested at all, but Pasteur has found them more than one reason.
1. Move one: capturing others' interests
How has Pasteur succeeded in capturing
the interests of other indifferent groups? By the same method he has always
used (Geison, 1974; SalomonBayet, 1982). He transfers himself and
his laboratory into the mist of a world untouched by laboratory science.
Beer, wine, vinegar, diseases of silk worms, antisepsy and later asepsy,
had already been treated through these moves. Once more he does the same
with a new problem: anthrax. The anthrax disease was said to be terrible
for French cattle. This 'terrible' character was 'proven' by statistics
to officials, veterinarians and farmers and their concerns were voiced
by the many agricultural societies of the time. This disease was studied
by statisticians and veterinarians, but laboratory practice had no bearing
on it before Pasteur, Koch and their disciples. At the time, diseases were
local events that were to be studied with all possible attention by taking
into account all the possible variablesóthe soil, the winds, the
Give me a labaratory...
145
weather, the farming system, and even
the individual fields, animals and farmers. Veterinary doctors knew these
idiosyncrasies, but it was a careful, variable, prudent and uncertain knowledge.
The disease was unpredictable, and recurred according to no clear pattern,
reinforcing the idea that local idiosyncrasies had to be taken into account.
This multifactorial approach made everyone extremely suspicious of any
attempt to cut through all these idiosyncrasies and to link one disease
with any single cause, such as a microorganism. Diseases like anthrax
with all their variations, were typically what was thought not to be related
to laboratory science. A lab in Paris and a farm in Beauce have nothing
in common. They are mutually uninteresting.
But interests, like everything else,
can be constructed. Using the work of many predecessors who had already
started to link laboratories and anthrax disease, Pasteur goes one step
further and works in a makeshift laboratory right on the farm site. No
two places could be more foreign to one another than a dirty, smelling,
noisy, disorganized nineteenthcentury animal farm and the obsessively
clean Pasteurian laboratory. In the first, big animals are parasited in
seemingly random fashion by invisible diseases; in the second, microorganisms
are made visible to the observer's eye. One is made to grow big animals,
the other to grow small animals. Pasteur (the 'shepherd' in French) is
often seen in the enthusiasm of the moment as the inventor of a new animal
husbandry and a new agriculture, but at the time these two forms of livestock
have little relation to one another. Once out in the field however, Pasteur
and his assistants learn from the field conditions and the veterinarians
and start creating these relations. They are interested in pinpointing
all the variations in the onset and timing of the outbreaks of anthrax
and in seeing how far these could fit with their one living cause, the
anthrax bacillus. They learn from the field, translating each item of veterinary
science into their own terms so that working on their terms is also working
on the field. For instance, the spore of the bacillus (shown by Koch) is
the translation through which dormant fields can suddenly become infectious
even after many years. The 'spore phase' is the laboratory translation
of the 'infected field' in the farmer's language. The Pasteurians start
by learning this language and giving one of their own names for each of
the relevant elements of the farmer's life. They are interested in the
field but still useless and uninteresting for the farmers and their various
spokesmen.
146
2. Move two: moving the leverage
point from a weak to a strong position
Bruno Latour
At this point Pasteur, having situated
his laboratory on the farm, is going to transfer it back to his main workplace
at the Ecole Normale Superieure, taking with him one element of the field,
the cultivated bacillus. He is the master of one technique of farming that
no farmer knows, microbe farming. This is enough to do what no farmer could
ever have done: grow the bacillus in isolation and in such a large quantity
that, although invisible, it becomes visible. Here again we have, because
of laboratory practice, a variation of scale: outside, in the 'real' world,
inside the bodies, anthrax bacilli are mixed with millions of other organisms
with which they are in a constant state of competition. This makes them
doubly invisible. However, in Pasteur's laboratory something happens to
the anthrax bacillus that never happened before (I insist on these two
points: something happens to the bacillus that never happened
before). Thanks to Pasteur's methods of culture it is freed from all competitors
and so grows exponentially, but, by growing so much, ends up, thanks to
Koch's later method, in such large colonies that a clearcut pattern
is made visible to the watchful eye of the scientist. The latter's skills
are not miraculous. To achieve such a result you only need to extract one
microorganism and to find a suitable milieu. Thanks to these skills,
the asymmetry in the scale of several phenomena is mod)fied: a microorganism
can kil1 vastly larger cattle, one small laboratory can learn more about
pure anthrax cultures than anyone before; the invisible microorganism
is made visible; the until now uninteresting scientist in his lab can talk
with more authority about the anthrax bacillus than veterinarians ever
have before.
The translation that allows Pasteur
to transfer the anthrax disease to his laboratory in Paris is not a literal,
wordforword translation. He takes only one element with him,
the microorganism, and not the whole farm, the smell, the cows, the
willows along the pond or the farmer's pretty daughter. With the microbe,
however, he also draws along with him the now interested agricultural societies.
Why? Because having designated the microorganism as the living and
pertinent cause, he can now reformulate farmers' interests in a new way:
if you wish to solve your anthrax problem you have to pass through
my laboratory first. Like all translations there is a real displacement
through the various versions. To go straight at anthrax, you should
make a detour through Pasteur's lab. The anthrax disease is now
at the Ecole Normale Superieure.
Give me a laboratory...
147
But this version of the translation
is still a weak one. In Pasteur's lab, there is a microbe, but anthrax
infection is too disorderly a thing to be explained with a single cause
only. So the outside interests could as wel1 say that the laboratory has
no real bearing on the spread of anthrax disease, and that it is just plain
arrogance for a scientist to claim that he holds the key to a real disease
'out there'. But Pasteur is able to make a more faithful translation than
that. Inside the walls of his laboratory, he can indeed inoculate animals
he has chosen with pure, muchdiluted culture of anthrax. This time,
the outbreak of an epizootic is mimicked on a smaller scale entirely dominated
by the charting and recording devices of the Pasteurians. The few points
deemed essential are imitated and reformulated so as to be scaled down.
The animals die of the microbes, and only of that, and epizootics are started
at will. It can now be said that Pasteur has inside his laboratory, on
a smaller scale, the 'anthrax disease'. The big difference is that 'outside'
it is hard to study because the microorganism is invisible and strikes
in the dark, hidden among many other elements, while 'inside' the lab clear
figures can be drawn about a cause that is there for all to see, due to
the translation. The change of scale makes possible a reversal of the actors'
strengths; 'outside' animals, farmers and veterinarians were weaker
than the invisible anthrax bacillus; inside Pasteur's lab, man becomes
stronger than the bacillus, and as a corollary, the scientist in his lab
gets the edge over the local, devoted, experienced veterinarian. The translation
has become more credible and now reads: 'If you wish to solve your anthrax
problem, come to my laboratory, because that's where the forces are reversed.
If you don't (veterinarians or farmers) you will be eliminated.'
But even at this point, the strength
is so disproportionate between Pasteur's single lab and the multiplicity,
complexity and economic size of the anthrax outbreaks, that no translation
could last long enough to keep the aggregation of interest from falling
apart. People readily give their attention to someone who claims that he
has the solution to their problems but are quick to take it back. Especially
puzzling for all practitioners and farmers, is the variation of
the disease. Sometimes it kills, sometimes not, sometimes it is strong,
sometimes weak. No contagionist theory can account for this variety. So
Pasteur's work, although interesting, could soon become a curiosity or
more precisely, a laboratory curiosity. It would not be the first time
that scientists attract attention, only to have nothing come out of it
in the end. Microstudies remain 'micro', the interests captured for a time
soon go to other translations from groups that succeed in enrolling them.
148
Bruno Latour
This was especially true of medicine
which at the time was tired of continuous fashions and fads (Leonard, 1977).
But here Pasteur does something on
chicken cholera and on anthrax bacillus inside his laboratory that definitively
mod)fies the hierarchy between veterinary science and microbiology. Once
a great many microbes are cultivated in pure forms in laboratories and
submitted to numerous trials to make them accelerate their growth or die,
a new practical knowhow is developed. In a few years, experimenters
acquire skills in manipulating sets of materials that never existed before.
This is new but not miraculous. Training microbes and domesticating them
is a craft like printing, electronics, blueribbon cooking or video
art. Once these skills have accumulated inside laboratories, many crossovers
occur that had no reason to occur anywhere else before. This is not because
of any new cog~utive attitude, or because suddenly people become conscious
of microorganisms they were unaware of before. It is simply that they
are manipulating new objects and so acquiring new skills in a new idiosyncratic
setting (Knorr, 1981).
The chance encounter that made possible
the first attenuated culture of chicken cholera is wellknown (Geison,
1974), but chance favours only wellprepared laboratories. Living causes
of manmade diseases undergo so many various trials that it is not
that surprising if some of these trials leave some microbes alive but weak.
This mod)fication would have been invisible if the laboratory had not tried
to imitate the salient features of epizootics by inoculating many animals.
The invisible mod)fication of the invisible microbes is then made visible;
chickens previously inoculated with the mod)fied strain don't get cholera
but they resist inoculation of intact microbes. Submitting cultures of
chicken cholera to oxygen is enough to make them less virulent when they
are inoculated into the animals. What is made visible through the lab statistics
is the chain of weakened microbes, then strengthened microbes and eventually,
strengthened animals. The result is that laboratories are now able to imitate
the variation of virulence.
It is important to understand that
Pasteur now does more and more things inside his laboratory which are deemed
relevant by more and more groups to their own interests. Cultivating the
microbes was a curiosity; reproducing epizootics in labs was interesting;
but varying at will the virulence of the microbes is fascinating. Even
if they believed in contagion, no one could with this one cause explain
the randomness ofthe effects. But Pasteur is not only the man who
has proved the relation of one microbe/one disease, he is also the one
who has proved that the infectiousness of microbes could vary under conditions
that
Give me a laboratory...
149
could be controlled, one of them being,
for instance, a first encounter of the body with a weakened form of the
disease. This variation in the laboratory is what makes the translation
hard for others to dispute: the variation was the most puzzling element
that previously just)fied the scepticism towards laboratory science, and
made necessary a clear differentiation between an outside and inside, between
a practical level and a theoretical level. But it is precisely this variation
that Pasteur can imitate most easily. He can attenuate a microbe; he can,
by passing it through different species of animals, on the contrary, exalt
its strength; he can oppose one weak form to a strong one, or even one
microbial species to another. To sum up, he can do inside his laboratory
what everyone tries to do outside but, where everyone fails because the
scale is too large, Pasteur succeeds because he works on a small scale.
Hygienists who comprise the largest relevant social movement of that time
are especially fascinated by this imitated variation. They deal with whole
cities and countries, trying to pinpoint why winds, soil, climates, diets,
crowding, or different degrees of wealth accelerate or stop the evolution
of epidemics. They all seeóthey are all led to seeóin the
Pasteurian microcosmos what they are vainly trying to do at the macroscopic
level. The translation is now the following: 'If you wish to understand
epizootics and soon thereafter epidemics, you have one place to go, Pasteur's
laboratory, and one science to learn that will soon replace yours: microbiology.'
As the reader is aware, I am multiplying
the words 'inside' and 'outside', 'micro' and 'macro', 'small scale' and
'large scale', so as to make clear the destabilizing role of the laboratory.
It is through laboratory practices that the complex relations between microbes
and cattle, the farmers and their cattle, the veterinarians and the farmers,
the veterinarians and the biological sciences, are going to be transformed.
Large interest groups consider that a set of lab studies talk to them,
help them and concern them. The broad concerns of French hygiene and veterinary
sciences will be settled, they all say, inside Pasteur's laboratory. This
is the dramatic short circuit I started with: everyone is interested in
lab experiments which a few years before had not the slightest relation
to their fields. This attraction and capture were made by a double movement
of Pasteur's laboratory to the field and then from the field to the laboratory
where a fresh source of knowhow has been gained by manipulating a
new material: pure cultures of microbes.
150
Bruno Latour
3. Move three: moving the world
with the lever
But even at this stage, what was in
the laboratory could have stayed there. Thc macrocosmos is linked to the
microcosmos of the laboratory, but a laboratory is never bigger than its
walls and 'Pasteur'is still only one man with a few collaborators. No matter
how great the interests of many social groups for what is being done in
one laboratory, there is nothing to stop interests from fading and dispersing
if nothing more than laboratory studies happens. If Pasteur stays too long
inside his laboratory and, for instance, shifts his research programme
using the anthrax microbe to learn things in biochemistry, like his disciple
Duclaux, people could say: 'Well after all, it was just an interesting
curiosity!' It is only by hindsight that we say that in this year 1881,
Pasteur invented the first art)ficial vaccination. By doing so we forget
that to do so it was necessary to move still further, this time from the
laboratory to the field, from the microscale to the macroscale. As for
all translations it is possible and necessary to distort the meanings but
not to betray them entirely. Groups that accepted to pass through Pasteur's
hands in order to solve their problems, nevertheless only go through him
to their own ends. They cannot stop in his laboratory.
Pasteur, from the start of his career,
was an expert at fosterir~g interest groups and persuading their members
that their interests wele inseparable from his own. He usually achieved
this fusion of interests (Callon, 1981) through the common use of some
laboratory practices. With anthrax he does just that but on a more grandiose
scale, since he is now attracting the attention of groups that are the
mouthpiece of larger social movements (veterinary science, hygiene, soon
medicine), and about issues that are the order of the day. As soon as he
has performed vaccinations in his laboratory he organizes a field trial
on a larger scale.
This field experiment was organized
under the auspices of the agricultural societies. Their attention had been
captured by Pasteur's former moves, but the translation ('solve your problems
through Pasteur's lab') implied that their problems could be solved
and not only Pasteur's. So the translation is also understood in part as
a contract, the counterpart of which is now expected from Pasteur. 'We
are ready to displace all our interests through your methods and practices
so that we can use them to reach our own goals.' This new translation (or
displacement) is as hard to negotiate as the first one. Pasteur has vaccine
for anthrax in his laboratory at Paris. But how can laboratory practice
be extended? In spite of all the niceties written by epistemologists on
that point, the answer is simple: only by extending the laboratory
itself. Pasteur cannot just hand out
a few flasks of vaccine to farmers and say: 'OK, it works in my lab, get
by with that.' If he were to do that, it would not work. The vaccination
can work only on the condition that the farm chosen in the village of Pouilly
le Fort for the field trial be in some crucial respects transformed according
to the prescriptions of Pasteur's laboratory. A hard negotiation ensues
between Pasteurians and agricultural interests on the conditions of the
experiment. How many inoculations? Who will be the umpire? And so on. This
negotiation is symmetrical to the initial one when Pasteur came to the
farm site, trying to extract the few pertinent elements of the disease
that he could imitate inside his laboratory. Here, the problem is to find
a compromise that extends Pasteur's laboratory far enoughóso that
the vaccination can be repeated and workóbut which is still acceptable
to the farming representatives so that it is seen as an extension of lab
science outside. If the extension is overreached, the vaccination will
fail and Pasteur will be thrown back inside his laboratory by the disappointed
farmers. If the extension is too modest, the same thing will happen: Pasteur
will be considered to be a lab scientist uninteresting for others' outside
use.
The Pouilly le Fort field trial is
the most famous of all the dramatic proofs that Pasteur staged in his long
career. The major mass media of the time were assembled on three successive
occasions to watch the unfolding of what was seen as Pasteur's prediction.
'Staging'is the right word because, in practice, it is the public showing
of what has been rehearsed many times before in his laboratory. It is strictly
speaking a repetition, but this time in front of an assembled public which
has previously invested so much interest and is now expecting its rewards.
Even the best performer has stage fright, even if everything has been well
rehearsed. Indeed this is what happened (Geison, 1974). But for the media
it was not seen as a performance, it was seen as a prophecy. The reason
behind this belief shows us exactly why the distinction between inside
and outside of the laboratory is so misleading. If you isolate Pasteur's
laboratory from the Pouilly le Fort farm, so that one is the inside and
the other is the outside world, then of course there is a miracle for all
to see. In his lab Pasteur says, 'all vaccinated animals will be alive
by the end of May; all the untreated animals will have died by the end
of May; and outside the lab the animals die or survive'. Miracle. Prophecy,
as good as that of Apollo. But if you watch carefully the prior displacement
of the laboratory to capture farmers' interest, then to learn from veterinary
sciences, then to transform the farm back into the guise of a laboratory,
it is still interesting, extraordinarily clever and ingenious, but it is
not a miracle. I will show later that most
152
Bruno Latour
of the mystified versions of scientific
activity come from overlooking such displacements of laboratories.
But there is still one step to make
so that we reach our point of departure: the anthrax outbreaks and their
impact on French agriculture. Remember that I said it was a 'terrible'
disease. While saying this I heard my ethnomethodologist friends jumping
on their chairs and screaming that no analyst should say that 'a disease
is terrible' or that 'French agriculture' exists, but rather that these
are social constructions. Indeed they are. Watch now how the Pasteur group
is going to use these constructions to their advantage and to France's.
Pouilly le Fort was a staged experiment to convince the investorsóin
confidence and later in moneyóthat the translation made by Pasteur
was a fair contract. 'If you want to solve your anthrax problem go through
my microbiology.' But after Pouilly le Fort, everyone is convinced that
the translation is now: 'If you want to save your animals from anthrax,
order a vaccine flask from Pasteur's laboratory, Ecole Normale Superieure,
rue d'Ulm, Paris.' In other words, on the condition that you respect a
limited set of laboratory practicesódisinfection, cleanliness, conservation,
inoculation gesture, timing and recordingó you can extend to every
French farm a laboratory product made at Pasteur's lab. What was at first
a capture of interest by a lab scientist is now extending through a network
much like a commercial circuitó not quite since Pasteur sends his
doses free of chargeóthat spreads laboratory products all over France.
But is 'all over France' a social construction?
Yes indeed; it is a construction made by statisticsgathering institutions.
Statistics is a major science in the nineteenth century, and is what 'Pasteur',
now the label for a larger crowd of Pasteurians, is going to use to watch
the spread of the vaccine, and to bring to the still uncertain public a
fresh and more grandiosely staged proof of the efficacy of the vaccine.
Throughout France as it is geographically marked out by its centralized
bureaucracy, one can register on beautifully done maps and diagrams the
decrease of anthrax wherever the vaccine is distributed. Like an experiment
in the Pasteur lab, statisticians inside the office of the agricultural
institutions are able to read on the charts the decreasing slopes that
mean, so they say, the decrease of anthrax. In a few years, the transfer
of the vaccine produced in Pasteur's lab to all farms was recorded in the
statistics as the cause of the decline of anthrax. Without these statistical
institutions it would of course have been utterlY impossible to say whether
the vaccine was of any use, as it would have been utterly impossible to
detect the existence of the disease to begin with.
Give me a laboratory...
153
We have now reached the point we started
from. French society, in some of its important aspects, has been transformed
through the displacements of a few laboratories.
II. Topology of laboratory
positioning
I have chosen one example but many
could be found in Pasteur's career and I am confident that every reader
has many more of these in mind. The reason why we do not acknowledge these
many examples is to be found in the way we treat science. We use a model
of analysis that respects the very boundary between micro and macroscale,
between inside and outside, that sciences are designed to not respect.
We all see laboratories but we ignore their construction, much like the
Victorians who watched kids crawling all over the place, but repressed
the vision of sex as the cause of
this proliferation. We are all prudish in matters of science, social scientists
included. Before drawing some general conclusions about laboratories in
the third part, let me propose a few concepts that would make us become
less prudish and would help to liberate all the information that we cannot
help having.
1. Dissolution of the inside/outside
dichotomy
Even in the brief outline given above,
the example I have chosen is enough to show that, at worst, the categories
of inside and outside are totally shaken up and fragmented by lab positioning.
But what word can be used that could help us to describe what happened,
including this reversion leading to the breaking down of inside/outside
dichotomies? I have used several times the words 'translation' or 'transfer',
'displacement' or 'metaphor', words that all say the same thing in Latin,
Greek or English (Serres, 1974; Callon, 1975). One thing is sure throughout
the story told above: every actor you can think of has been to some extent
displaced (Armatte, 1981).
Pasteur's lab is now in the middle of agricultural interests with which
it had no relation before; in the farms an element coming from Paris, vaccine
flasks, has been added; veterinary doctors have mod)fied their status by
promoting 'Pasteur's' science and the vaccine flasks: they now possess
one more weapon in their black bags; and sheep and cows are now freed from
a terrible death: they can give more milk and more wool to the farmer and
be slaughtered with greater profit. In McNeil's terms (McNeil, 1976), the
154
Bruno Latour
displacement of microparasites allows
the macroparasitesóhere the farmersóto grow fatter by feeding
off healthier cattle. By the same token all the macroparasitic chain of
tax collectors, veterinarians, administrators and landlords prosper by
feeding off the richer farmers (Serres, 1980). One last element is pushed
outóthe anthrax bacillus. Wherever the veterinarian comes the small
parasite has to go. In this succession of displacements, no one can say
where the laboratory is and where the society is. Indeed
the question 'where?' is an irrelevant one when you deal with displacements
from a lab in Paris to some farms then back to Paris, drawing along
with it the microbes and the farmers' interests; then to Pouilly le Fort
where an extended repetition is staged, then to the whole agricultural
system through statistics and bureaucracy. But it is clear that the situation
of the farms after the moves is not the same as before. Through the leverage
point of the lab, which is a moment in a dynamic process, the farm system
has been displaced. It now includes a routine annual gesture, part of which
used to be a laboratory practice and still is a lab product. Everyone has
changed, including the 'whole society', to use common terms. This is why
I used in the title a parody of Archimedes's famous motto: 'give me a laboratory
and I'll move the earth'. This metaphor of the lever to move something
else is much more in keeping with observation than any dichotomy between
a science and a society. In other words, it is the same set of forces that
drives people inside Pasteurian labs to strengthen microbiology and outside
to stage the Pouilly le Fort experiment or to modify French agriculture.
What we will have to understand later is why in this moment the
laboratory gains strength to modify the state of affairs of all the other
actors.
Another reason why the inside/outside
notion is irrelevant, is that in this example the laboratory positions
itself precisely so as to reproduce inside its walls an event that seems
to be happening only outsideóthe first moveóand then to extend
outside to all farms what seems to be happening only inside laboratories.
As in some topological theorem, the inside and the outside world can reverse
into one another very easily. Naturally, the three relations outside, inside,
outside again, are in no way identical. Only a few elements of the macroscopic
epizootics are captured in the lab, only controlled epizootics on experimer~tal
animals are done in the lab, only specific inoculation gestures and vaccine
inoculant are extracted out of the lab to be spread to farms. That this
metaphorical drift, which is made of a succession of displacements and
changes of scale (see below p~l64), is the source of all innovations is
well known (Black, 1961). For our purpose here, it is enough to say
Give me a laboratory.. .
155
that each translation from one position
to the next is seen by the captured actors to be a faithful translation
and not a betrayal, a deformation or something absurd. For instance, the
disease in a Petri dish, no matter how far away from the farm situation,
is seen as a faithful . translation, indeed the interpretation of
anthrax disease. The same~ thing is true when hygienists see as equivalent
the trials microbes undergo in Pasteur's lab, and the variations of epidemics
that masses of people undergo in a large city like Paris. It is useless
trying to decide if these two settings are really equivalentóthey
are not since Paris is not a Petri dishóbut they are deemed equivalent
by those who insist that if Pasteur solves his microscale problems the
secondary macroscale problem will be solved. The negotiation on the equivalence
of nonequivalent situations is always what characterizes the spread of
a science, and what explains, most of the time, why there are so many laboratories
involved every time a difficult negotiation has to be settled.
For the vaccine to be effective, it
has to spread outside in the 'real world out there', as people say. This
is what best shows the absurdity of the dichotomy between inside/outside
and the usefulness of microstudies of science in understanding macroissues.
Most of the difficulties associated with science and technology come from
the idea that there is a time when innovations are in laboratories, and
another time when they are tried out in a new set of conditions which invalidate
or verify the efficacy of these innovations. This is the 'adequatio rei
et intellectus' that fascinates epistemologists so much. As this example
shows, the reality of it is more mundane and less mystical.
First, the vaccine works at Pouilly
le Fort and then in other places only if in all these places the same laboratory
conditions are extended there beforehand. Scientific facts are like trains,
they do not work off their rails. You can extend the rails and connect
them but you cannot drive a locomotive through a field. The best proof
of this is that every time the method of extension of the anthrax vaccine
was mod)fied, the vaccine did not
work and Pasteur got
bogged down in bitter controversy, for instance with the Italians (Geison,
1974). His answer was always to check and see if everything was done according
to the prescriptions of his lab. That the same thing can be repeated does
not strike me as miraculous, but it does seem to be for all the people
who imagine that facts get out of laboratories without the extension of
lab practices.
But there is a second reason why the
laboratories have no outside. The very existence of the anthrax disease
in the first place, and the very efficacy of the vaccine at the end of
the story, are not 'outside'
156
Bruno Latour
facts given for all to see. They are,
in both cases, the result of the prior existence of statistical institutions
having built an instrument (statistics in this case), having extended their
network through the whole French administration so as to gather data, and
having convinced all the of ficials that there was a 'disease', a 'terrible'
one, and that there was a 'vaccine', an 'efficient' one. Most of the time
when we talk about the outside world we are simply taking for granted
the prior extension of a former science built on the same principle
as the one we are studying. This is why lab studies in the end hold the
key to the understanding of macroproblems, as I will show at the end of
this chapter.
2 Playing havoc with differences
of scale
But if the inside/outside dichotomy
does not hold true, what are we going to say about differences of scale
which, the reader should be reminded, are at the origin of many discussions
in sociology of science, since it is because of this belief in differences
of scale that microstudies are accused of missing some essential points?
In the example I sketched out above, we are never confronted with a social
context on one hand and a science, laboratory, or individual scientist
on the other. We do not have a context influencing, or not influencing,
a laboratory immune from social forces. This view, which is the dominant
view among most sociologists, is exactly what is untenable. Of course,
many good scholars like Geison could show why the fact that Pasteur is
a Catholic, a conservative, a chemist, a Bonapartist, etc., do count (Farley
and Geison, 1979). But this sort of analysis, no matter how careful and
interesting, would entirely miss the main point: in his very scientipc
work, in the depth of his laboratory, Pasteur actively modifies the society
of his time and he does so directly ónot indirectlyóby
displacing some of its most important actors.
Here again Pasteur is a paradigmatic
example. As a politician he failed so completely that he was unable to
get more than a few votes the few times he tried to get elected senator.
But he has along with Carnot, and the Republic itself, the greatest number
of streets bearing his name in all French villages and towns. This is also
a nice symbol of the studies about Pasteur. If you look for examples of
his 'politicking' politics, you will of course find them but they are poor,
disappointing, and never in keeping with the importance of his scientific
work. The poverty of your findings will make readers say that 'there is
something else in Pasteur, in his scientific achievements, that escapes
all social or
Give me a laboratory...
157
political explanation'. People who
would utter this cliche would indeed be right. A poor critical explanation
always protects science. This is why the more radical scientists write
against science, the more science is mystified and protected.
To study Pasteur as a man acting on
society, it is not necessary to search for political drives, for some shortterm
monetary or symbolic profits or for longterm chauvinistic motives.
It is no use looking for unconscious ideologies or devious drives (drives
which, by some mystery, are clear only to the analyst's eyes). It is no
use muckraking. You just have to look at what he does in his laboratory
as a scientist. To summarize a long study in a nutshell (Latour, 1981a),
Pasteur adds to all the forces that composed French society at the time
a new force for which he is the only credible spokesmanóthe microbe.
You cannot build economic relations without this 'tertium quid' since the
microbe if unknown, can bitter your beer, spoil your wine, make the mother
of your vinegar sterile, bring back cholera with your goods, or kill your
factotum sent to India. You cannot build a hygienist social movement without
it, since no matter what you do for the poor masses crowded in shanty towns,
they will still die if you do not control this invisible agent. You cannot
establish even innocent relations between a mother and her son, or a lover
and his mistress, and overlook the agent that makes the baby die of diptheria
and has the client sent to the mad house because of syphilis. You do not
need to muckrake or look for distorted ideologies to realize that a group
of people, equipped with a laboratory the only place where the invisible
agent is made visibleó will easily be situated everywhere in all
these relations, wherever the microbe can be seen to intervene. If you
reveal microbes as essential actors in all social relations, then you need
to make room for them and for the people who show them and can eliminate
them. Indeed the more you want to get rid of the microbes, the more room
you should grant Pasteurians. This is not.false consciousness, this is
not looking for biased world views, this is just what the Pasteurians did
and the way they were seen by all the other actors of the time.
The congenital weakness of the sociology
of science is its propensity to look for obvious stated political motives
and interests in one of the only places, the laboratories, where sources
of fresh politics as yet unrecognized as such are emerging. If by politics
you mean elections and law, then Pasteur, as I have said, was not driven
by political interests, except in a few marginal aspects of his science.
Thus his science is protected from enquiry and the myth of the autonomy
of science is saved. If by politics you mean to be the spokesman of the
forces you
L58
Bruno Latour
mould society with and of which you
are the only credible and legitimate authority, then Pasteur is a fully
political man. Indeed, he endows himself with one of the most striking
fresh sources of power ever. Who can imagine being the representative of
a crowd of invisible, dangerous forces able to strike anywhere and to make
a shambles of the present state of society, forces of which he is by definition
the only credible interpreter and which only he can control? Everywhere
Pasteurian laboratories were established as the only agency able to kill
the dangerous actors that were until then perverting efforts to make beer,
vinegar, to perform surgery, to give birth, to milk a cow, to keep a regiment
healthy and so on. It would be a weak conception of sociology if the reader
were only to say that microbiology 'has an influence' or 'is influenced
by the nineteenthcentury social context'. Microbiology laboratories
are one of the few places where the very composition of the social context
has been metamorphosed. It is not a small endeavour to transfcrm society
so as to include microbes and microbewatchers in its very fabric.
If the reader is not convinced, then he can compare the sudden moves made
at the same time by socialist politicians, talking on behalf of another
crowd of new, dangerous, undisciplined and disturbing forces for whom room
should be made in society: the labouring masses. The two powers are comparable
in this essential feature: they are fresh sources of power for modifying
society and cannot be explained by the state of the society at the time.
Although the two powers were mixed together at the time (Rozenkranz, 1972),
it is clear that in political terms the influence of Pasteurian laboratories
reached further, deeper, and more irreversibly since they could intervene
in the daily details of lifeóspitting, boiling milk, washing handsó
and at the macroscaleórebuilding sewage systems, colonizing countries,
rebuilding hospitalsówithout ever being clearly seen as a stated
political power.
This transformation of what is the
very composition of society can in no way be defined through distinctions
of scales and of levels. Neither the historian nor the sociologist can
distinguish the macrolevel of French society and the microlevel of the
microbiology laboratory, since the latter is helping to redefine and displace
the former. The laboratory positioning, as I insisted on earlier, was in
no way inevitable. Pasteur could have failed to link his work on microbes
to his many clients' interests. Had he failed, then I agree that the distinction
of levels would hold true: there would indeed be French agricultural, medical,
social, political interests on the one hand, and the insulated laboratory
of a disinterested scientist at the Ecole Normale Superieure
Give me a laboratory...
159
on the other. Claude Bernard had such
a laboratory. But this was in no way Pasteur's strategy, and still less
that of the larger Institut Pasteur, which was always situated in such
a way that all the interested commercial, colonial, and medical interests
had to pass through their laboratories to borrow the technics, the gestures,
the products, the diagnostic kits that were necessary to further their
own desires. Laboratories were set up everywhere: on the front line during
the first world war in the trenches they largely made possible; before
the colonists arrived in the tropics, allowing the very survival of the
white colonists and their soldiers; in the surgery ward that was transformed
from a teaching amphitheatre into a laboratory (SalomonBayet, 1982);
in the plants of the food industries in many public health services; inside
the small offices of general practitioners; in the midst of farms, and
so on. Give us laboratories and we will make possible the Great War without
infection, we wil1 open tropical countries to colonization, we will make
France's army healthy, we will increase the number and strength of her
inhabitants, we will create new industries. Even blind and deaf analysts
will see these claims as 'social' activity, but on condition that laboratories
are considered places where society and politics are renewed and transformed.
III. How the weakest becomes
the strongest
What I have said about the example
treated in Part I now leads us to the more general problem of laboratory
practice and of the relevance of microstudies for understanding the 'largescale'
problems raised by the field known as Science, Technology and Society (STS).
If I were to summarize the argument presented in Part II I could say that
a sociology of science hamstrings itself from the start: if, that is, it
takes for granted the difference of levels or of scale between the 'social
context' on the one hand and the laboratory or the 'scientific level' on
the other; and if it fails to study the very content of what is
being done inside the laboratories. I claim that, on the contrary, laboratories
are among the few places where the differences of scale are made irrelevant
and where the very content of the trials made within the walls of the laboratory
can alter the composition of society. The methodological consequence of
this argument is, of course, that we were right in starting with onthespot
laboratory studies and looking for a sociology of the contents of
science (Latour and Woolgar, 1979). It is not only the key to a sociological
understanding of science that is to be found in
160
Bruno Latour
lab studies, it is also, I believe,
the key to a sociological understanding of society itself, since it is
in laboratories that most new sources of power are generated. Sociology
of science cannot always be borrowing from sociology or social history
the categories and concepts to reconstruct the 'social context' inside
which science should be understood. On the contrary, it is time for sociology
of science to show sociologists and social historians how societies are
displaced and reformed with and through the very contents of science. But
to do so, sociologists of scientific practice should avoid being shy and
sticking only to the level of the laboratory (for this level does not exist)
and being proud of diving inside laboratory walls, because laboratories
are the places where the inside/outside relations are reversed. In other
words, since laboratory practices lead us constantly inside/outside and
upside/down, we should be faithful to our field and follow our objects
throughout all their transformations. This is simply good methodology.
But to do so without getting dizzy, we should understand in more detail
the strange topology that laboratory practices present.
The most difficult problem for understanding
this positioning of laboratory practice is to define precisely why it is
that in the laboratory and only there new sources of strength are generated.
Using the metaphor of the lever, why is a laboratory a solid lever and
not a soft straw? In asking this question we are back to the problem of
understanding what has been achieved through microstudies of science. Many
answers were given by epistemologists before lab studies started pouring
in. It was said that scientists had special methods, special minds, or
in more culturalist forms of racism, some kind of special culture. It was
always in something 'special', usually of a cognitive quality, that this
source of strength was explained. Of course, the moment sociologists walked
into laboratories and started checking all these theories about the strength
of science, they just disappeared. Nothing special, nothing extraordinary,
in fact nothing of any cognitive quality was occurring there. Epistemologists
had chosen the wrong objects, they looked for mental aptitudes and ignored
the material local setting, that is, laboratories. The same thing happened
with most of the socalled Mertonian sociology. No special sociological
relations could explain anything about the strength of science. The 'norms'
faded away like the 'invisible college' and the 'precapitalist recognition
of debt', and went into the limbo where 'falsification', and the 'angels'
sexes' are put for a welldeserted eternal rest. The first sociologists
made the same mistake as the epistemologists. They looked for something
special everywhere except in the most obvious and striking place: the settings.
Even scientists themselves
Give me a laboratory....
161
are more aware of what makes them special
than many analysts. Pasteur, for instance, a better sociologist and epistemologist
than most, wrote a kind of treatise on sociology of science simply pointing
to the laboratory as the cause of the strength gained by scientist over
society (Pasteur, 1 871).
Laboratory studies have been successful,
but so far only in the negative sense of dissipating previous beliefs surrounding
science. Nothing special is happening in the cognitive and in the social
aspect of laboratory practice. KnorrCetina has reviewed this (this
volume, ch. 5) and there is nothing much else to add, nothing except that
we now have to explain what happens in laboratories that makes them such
an irreplaceable source of political strength, strength which is not
explained by any cognitive or social peculiarities.
In earlier work (Latour and Fabbri,
1977; Latour and Woolgar, 1979), I have indicated a line of enquiry to
answer this most tricky of all questions. This approach can be summed up
by the sentence: look at the inscription devices. No matter if people
talk about quasars, gross national products, statistics on anthrax epizootic
microbes, DNA or subparticle physics; the only way they can talk and not
be undermined by counterarguments as plausible as their own statements
is if, and only if, they can make the things they say they are talking
about easily readable. No matter the size, cost, length, and width of the
instruments they build, the final end product of all these inscription
devices is always a written trace that makes the perceptive judgment of
the others simpler. The race for the invention of these inscription
devices and for the simplification of the inscriptions provided leads either
to simple forms (dots, bands, peaks and spots) or, even better, to another
written text directly readable on the surface of the inscription. The result
of this exclusive interest in inscriptions is a text that limits the number
of counterarguments by displaying, for each difficult displacement,
one of these simplified inscriptions (diagrams, tables, pictures). The
purpose of the construction of this double text that includes arguments
and inscriptions is to alter the modalities a reader could add to the statements.
Moving a modality from 'it is probable that A is B', to 'X has shown that
A is B', is enough to obtain a scientific 'fact' (Latour and Woolgar, 1979:
ch. 2).
This kind of enquiry had the immense
advantage of revealing special features of the laboratory ó obsession
for inscription devices and writing specific types of texts which
left the rest of the setting completely ordinary. To take up Feyerabend's
saying: 'in the laboratory anything goes, except the inscription devices
and the papers'.
162
Bruno Latour
Scientific fact is the product of average,
ordinary people and settings, linked to one another by no special norms
or communication forms, but who work with inscription devices. This argument
which at first appeared reductionist and too simple has since received
much more support and is now well established. Semiotics (Bastide, 1981)
has demonstrated how far one can go in the content of science by looking
at this matter of the text itself, but it is from cognitive anthropology,
cognitive psychology, and history of science that stronger support is now
coming. The technology of inscribing (writing, schooling, printing, recording
procedures) is seen by more and more analysts as the main cause of what
was attributed in earlier times to 'cognitive' or 'vague cultural' phenomena.
The books of Jack Goody (1977), and above all of Elizabeth Eisenstein (1979),
show well the extraordinary fecundity of looking at this material level
that had escaped the attention of epistemologists, historians, sociologists
and anthropologists alike because inscription technology seemed to them
to be too obvious and too 'light'. This mysterious thinking process that
seemed to float like an inaccessible ghost over social studies of science
at last has flesh and bones and can be thoroughly examined. The mistake
before was to oppose heavy matter (or 'largescale' infrastructures
like in the first 'materialist' studies of science) to spiritual, cognitive
or thinking processes instead of focusing on the most ubiquitous and lightest
of all materials: the written one (Havelock, 1981; Dagognet, 1973).
But if we accept this approach, are
we not back again to the microlevel and far from the macroconcerns of all
the other analysts in STS, preoccupied by serious things like disarmament,
technology transfer, sociology of innovation or history of science? Looking
at the inscriptions is interesting one could say, but it leaves us with
a long way to go to explain how the strength is gained in laboratories
to transform or displace societies. This is precisely why the first laboratory
study I made was weak; it was weak for a simple methodological reason.
I focused on one laboratory, taking for granted its existence as a unit
and its relevance to the outside. So I had no occasion to watch the most
puzzling procedure of all, how a set of inscription procedures are made
to be relevant to issues which at first sight seem utterly foreign and
much too grandiose, complicated or disorderly ever to end up on the top
of a desk in a few easily read diagrams and charts discussed quietly by
a few whitecoated PhDs. The last point of this chapter will be to
formulate, thanks to Pasteur's strategy, the simple answer to this puzzle,
so simple indeed that it had escaped my attention.
The answer is visible if we bring together
the three threads of my
Give me a laboratory...
163
argument: the dissolution of the inside/outside
boundary; the inversion of scales and levels; and fnally the process of
inscription. These three themes point to the same problem: how a few people
gain strength and go inside some places to modify other places and the
life of the multitudes. Pasteur, for instance, and his few collaborators
cannot tackle the anthrax problem by moving all over France and gathering
an intimate knowledge of all the farms, farmers, animals and local idiosyncrasies.
The only place where they are able and good workers is in their laboratory.
Outside they are worse at farming than the farmers and worse at veterinary
medicine than the veterinarians. But they are expert inside their own walls
at setting up trials and instruments so that the invisible actorsówhich
they call microbes show their moves and development in pictures so
clear that even a child would see them. The invisible becomes visible and
the 'thing' becomes a written trace they can read at will as if it were
a text. This expertise, in their case, is already obtained by a complete
mod)fication of the scale. As has been previously explained, the microbe
is invisible as long as it is not cultivated in isolation from its other
competitors. As soon as it grows uninhibited on an aptly chosen medium,
it grows exponentially and makes itself large enough to be counted as small
dots on the Petri dish. I don't know what a microbe is, but counting dots
with clearcut edges on a white surface is simple. The problem now
is to link this expertise to the health field. I showed the solution earlier
by these threepronged movements that displace the laboratory. The
consequence is clear. By these moves an epizootic occurs inside the laboratory
walls that is deemed relevant to the macroproblems outside. Again the scale
of the problem is reversed, but this time it's the 'macro' that is made
small enough to be dominated by the Pasteurians. Before this displacement
and inversion that allowed Pasteurians to hook an expertise in setting
up inscription devices onto the health field, no one had ever been able
to master the course of an epidemic. This 'mastery' means that each eventóthe
inoculation, the outbreak of an epidemic, the vaccination, the counting
of the dead and of the living, the timing, the placesó becomes entirely
readable by a few men who could agree among themselves because of the simplicity
of each perceptive judgment they were able to make about simple diagrams
and curves.
The strength gained in the laboratory
is not mysterious. A few people much weaker than epidemics can become stronger
if they change the scale of the two actorsómaking the microbes big,
and the epizootic small and others dominate the events through the
inscription devices that make each of the steps readable. The change of
164
Bruno Latour
scale entails an acceleration in the
number of inscriptions you can get. Obtaining data on anthrax epidemics
on the scale of France was a slow, painstaking, and uncertain process.
But in a year Pasteur could multiply anthrax outbreaks. No wonder that
he became stronger than veterinarians. For every statistic they had, he
could mobilize ten of them. Before Pasteur, their statements could be interrupted
by any number of other statements just as plausible as theirs. But when
Pasteur comes out of his lab with this many figures who is able to mount
a serious attack against him? Pasteur has gained strength simply by modifying
the scale. So, in discussions about anthrax, Pasteur has two sources of
strength: the epizootic and the microbes. His opponents and predecessors
had to work 'outside' on a 'large scale', constantly stabbed in the back
haphazardly by the invisible agent that made their statistics look random.
But Pasteur, by building his laboratory and inserting it in the farms as
we have seen, dominates the microbeóthat he made biggeróand
the epizooticóthat he made smalleróand multiplies the experiments
at small cost without leaving his laboratory. This concentration
of forces makes him so much stronger than his competitors that they cannot
even think of a counterargument except in the few cases ~vhere, like
Koch, they are equipped as well as he is.
To understand the reason why people
pay so much for laboratories which are actually ordinary places, one just
has to consider these places as nice technological devices to invert the
hierarchy of forces. Thanks to a chain of displacementsóboth of
the laboratory and of the objectsóthe scale of what people want
to talk about is mod)fied so as to reach this best of all possible scales:
the inscription on a flat surface written in simple forms and letters.
Then everything they have to talk about is not only visible, but also readable,
and can be easily pointed at by a few people who by doing this dominate.
This is as simple and as aufficient as Archimedes's point about moving
the earth and making the weakest the strongest. It is simple indeed because
making simple moves is what this device is about. 'Accumulated knowledge'
people say with admiration, but this acceleration is made possible by a
change of scale, which in turn makes possible the multiplication of trials
and errors. Certainty does not increase in a laboratory because people
in it are more honest, more rigorous, or more 'falsificationist'. It is
simply that they can make as many mistakes as they wish or simply more
mistakes than the others 'outside' who cannot master the changes of scale.
Each mistake is in turn archived, saved, recorded, and made easily readable
again, whatever the specific field or topic may be. If a great many trials
are recorded and it is possible to make a sum of their inscriptions, that
Give me a laboratory...
165
sum will always be more certain if
it decreases the possibility of a competitor raising a statement as plausible
as the one you are defending. That is enough. When you sum up a series
of mistakes, you are stronger than anyone who has been allowed fewer mistakes
than you.
This vision of the laboratory as a
technological device to gain strength by multiplying mistakes, is made
obvious if one looks at the difference between a politician and a scientist.
They are typically contrasted on cognitive or social grounds. The first
is said to be greedy, full of selfinterest, shortsighted, fuzzy, always
ready to compromise, and shaky. The second is said to be disinterested,
farsighted, honest, or at least rigorous, to talk clearly and exactly
and to look for certainty. These many differences are all art)ficial projections
of one, simple, material thing. The politician has no laboratory and the
scientist has one. So the politician works on a ful1 scale, with only one
shot at a time, and is constantly in the limelight. He gets by, and wins
or loses 'out there'. The scientist works on scale models, multiplying
the mistakes inside his laboratory, hidden from public scrutiny. He can
try as many times as he wishes, and comes out only when he has made all
the mistakes that have helped him gain 'certainty'. No wonder that one
does not 'know' and the other 'knows'. The difference, however, is not
in 'knowledge'. If you could by chance reverse the positions, the same
greedy, shortsighted politician, once in a laboratory, is going to
churn out exact scientific facts, and the honest, disinterested, rigorous,
scientist put at the helm of a political structure that is full scale and
with no mistakes allowed will become fuzzy, uncertain and weak like everyone
else. The specificity of science is not to be found in cognitive, social
or psychological qualities, but in the special construction of laboratories
in a manner which reverses the scale of phenomena so as to make things
readable, and then accelerates the frequency of trials, allowing many mistakes
to be made and registered.
That the laboratory setting is the
cause of the strength gained by scientists is made still clearer when people
want to establish elsewhere conclusions as certain as those reached in
the laboratory. As I have shown above, it can be said that there is no
outside to laboratories. The best thing one can do is to extend to other
places the 'hierarchy of forces' that was once favourable inside the first
laboratory. I showed this for anthrax but it is a general case. The mystification
of science comes most often from the idea that scientists are able to make
'predictions'. They work in their labs and, sure enough, something happens
outside that verifies these predictions. The problem is that no one has
ever been able to verify these predictions without extending
166
Bruno Latour
first the conditions of verification
that existed in the laboratory. The vaccine extends on the condition that
farms are transformed into an annex of Pasteur's lab and that the very
statistical system that made anthrax visible in the first place is used
to verify if the vaccine had any effect. We can watch the extension of
laboratory conditions, and the repetition of the final trial that was favourable,
but we cannot watch predictions of scientists extending themselves beyond
laboratory walls (Latour and Woolgar, 1979: ch. 4).
If this seems counterintuitive
to the reader, a little reasoning will convince him that every counterexample
he can think of in fact conforms to the position stated here. No one has
ever seen a laboratory fact move outside unless the lab is first brought
to bear on an 'outside' situation and that situation is transformed so
that it fits laboratory prescriptions. Every counterexample is a belief
that such a thing is possible. But a belief is not a proof. If the proof
is given then the two conditions I stated will always be verified. My confidence
in this answer is not based on presumption but on a simple scientific belief,
shared by all my fellow scientists, that magic is impossible and that action
at a distance is always a misrepresentation. Scientists' predictions or
previsions are always postdictions or repetitions. The confirmation
of this obvious phenomenon is shown in scientific controversies when scientists
are forced to leave the solid ground of their laboratories. The moment
they really get 'outside' they know nothing, they bluff, they fail, they
get by, they lose all possibility to say anything that is not immediately
counterattacked by swarms of equally plausible statements.
The only way for a scientist to retain
the strength gained inside his laboratory by the process I have described
is not to go outside where he would lose it at once. It is again very simple.
The solution is in never going out. Does that mean that they are
stuck in the few places where they work? No. It means that they will do
everything they can to extend to every setting some of the conditions that
make possible the reproduction of favourable laboratory practices. Since
scientific facts are made inside laboratories, in order to make them circulate
you need to build costly networks inside which they can maintain their
fragile efficacy. If this means transforming society into a vast laboratory,
then do it. The spread of Pasteurian laboratories to all the places
that a few decades before had nothing to do with science is good example
of this network building. But a look at systems of Standard Weights and
Measures, called 'metrologie' in French, is still more convincing. Most
of the work done in a laboratory would stay there for ever if the
Give me a laboratory...
167
principal physical constants could
not be made constant everywhere else. Time, weight, length, wavelength,
etc., are extended to ever more localities and in ever greater degrees
of precision. Then and only then, laboratory experiments can be brought
to bear on problems occurring in factories, the tool industry, economics
or hospitals. But if you just try in a thought experiment to extend the
simplest law of physics 'outside', without first having extended and controlled
all the main constants, you just could not verify it, just as it would
have been impossible to know the existence of anthrax and to see the efficacy
of the vaccine without the health statistics. This transformation of the
whole of society according to laboratory experiments is ignored by sociologists
of science.
There is no outside of science but
there are long, narrow networks that make possible the circulation of scientific
facts. Naturally the reason for this ignorance is easy to understand. People
think that the universality of science is a given, because they forget
to take into account the size of the 'metrologie'. Ignoring this transformation
that makes all displacements possible is like studying an engine without
the railway or the freeway networks. The analogy is a good one since the
seemingly simple work of maintaining the physical constants constant in
a modern society is evaluated to be three times more than the effort of
all the science and technology themselves (Hunter, 1980). The cost of making
society conform to the inside of laboratories so that the latter's activity
can be made relevant to the society is constantly forgotten, because people
do not want to see that universality is a social construction as well (Latour,
1981b).
Once all these displacements and transformations
are taken into account, the distincticn between the macrosocial level and
the level of laboratory science appears fuzzy or even nonexistent.
Indeed, laboratories are built to destroy this distinction. Once it is
dissolved, a few people can inside their insulated walls work on things
that can change the daily life of the multitudes. No matter if they are
economists, physicists, geographers, epidemiologists, accountants, microbiologists,
they make all the other objects on such a scaleómaps, economic models,
figures, tables, diagrams that they can gain strength, reach incontrovertible
conclusions, and then extend on a larger scale the conclusions that seem
favourable to them. It is a
political process. It is not a
political process. It is since they gain a source of power. It is not since
it is a source of fresh power that escapes the routine and easy definition
of a stated political power. 'Give me a laboratory and I will move society',
I said, parodying Archimedes. We now know why a
168
Bruno Latour
laboratory is such a good lever. But if I now parody Clausewitz's motto, we will have a more complete picture: 'science is politics pursued by other means'. It is not politics since a power is always blocked by another counterpower. What counts in laboratory sciences are the other means, the fresh, unpredictable sources of displacements that are all the more powerful because they are ambiguous and unpredictable. Pasteur, representing the microbes and displacing everyone else, is making politics, but by other, unpredictable means that force everyone else out, including the traditional political forces. We can now understand why it was and is so important to stick to laboratory microstudies. In our modern societies most of the really fresh power comes from sciencesóno matter whichóand not from the classical political process. By staking all social explanations of science and technology on the classical view of politics and economicsóprofit, stated power, predictable evils or goodsóanalysts of science who claim to study the macrolevels fail to understand precisely what is strong in science and technology. In speaking of scientists who make politics by other means, their boring and repetitive critique is always that they 'just make politics', period. Their explanation falls short. The shortness of it is in the periodóthey stop where they should start. Why though are the means different? To study these other means, one must get inside the contents of the sciences, and inside the laboratories where the future reservoirs of political power are in the making. The challenge of laboratories to sociologists is the same as the challenge of laboratories to society. They can displace society and recompose it by the very content of what is done inside them, which seemed at first irrelevant or too technical. The careful scrutiny of laboratory scientists cannot be ignored and no one can jump from this 'level' to the macropolitical level since the latter gets all its really efficient sources of power from these very laboratories that have just been deemed uninteresting or too technical to be analyzed.
But we can also understand why students
of laboratory practices should not be shy and accept a vision of their
own method that would limit them to the laboratory, whereas the laboratory
is just a moment in a series of displacements that makes a complete shambles
out of the inside/outside and the macro/micro dichotomies. No matter how
divided they are on sociology of science, the macroanalysts and the microanalysts
share one prejudice: that science stops or begins at the laboratory
walls. The laboratory is a much trickier
object than that, it is a much more efficient transformer of forces than
that. That is why by remaining faithful to his method, the microanalyst
will end up
Give me a laboratory...
169
tackling macroissues as well, exactly
like the scientist doing lab experiments on microbes who ends up modifying
many details of the whole of French society. Indeed, I think an argument
could be made to show that the existence of the macrolevel itself, the
famous 'social context', is a consequence of the development of many scientific
disciplines (Callon and Latour, 1981). It is already clear to me that this
is the only way that sociology of science can be rebuilt in keeping with
the constraints now set by laboratory studies. I also think that it is
one of the few ways that sociology of science can teach something to sociology
instead of borrowing from it categories and social structures that the
simplest laboratory is destroying and recomposing. It would be high time,
since the laboratory is more innovative in politics and in sociology than
most sociologists (including many sociologists of science). We are only
just starting to take up the challenge that laboratory practices present
for the study of society.
References
Armatte, Michel(1981) Ca marche, les traductions
del'homme autravail, Meimoire de DEA, Paris: CNAMSTS.
Bastide, Françoise (1981) 'Le Foie Lave, analyse
semiotique d'un texte scientifique', Le Bulletin, 2: 35 82.
Black, Max (1961) Models and Metaphors, Ithaca,
NY: Comell University Press.
Callon, Michel (1975) 'Les Operations de Traductions',
in P. Roqueplo (ed.), Incidence des Rapports Socioux sur le De'veloppement
Scientifque, Paris: CNRS.
Callon, Michel (1981) 'Struggles and Negotiations
to Define What is Problematic and What is Not: The Sociologic Translation',
in K. Knorr, R. Krohn and R. Whitley (eds), The Social Process of Scientific
Investigation, Sociology of the Sciences Yearbook, vol. 4, Dordrecht:
D. Reidel.
Callon, Michel (1982) 'La Mort d'un Laboratoire Saisi
par l'Aventure Technologique' (in preparation).
Callon, Michel and Latour, Bruno (1981) 'Unscrewing
the Big Leviathan, or How do Actors Macrostructure Reality?', in K. D.
KnorrCetina and A. Cicourel (eds), Advances in Social Theory and
Methodology Toward an Integration of Micro and Macrosociologies, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Collins, H. M. (1975) 'The Seven Sexes: A Study in
the Sociology of a Phenomenon or the Replication of Experiments in Physics',
Sociology, 9 (2): 20524.
170Bruno Latour
Collins, H. M. (1982) 'Stages in the Empirical Programme
of Relativism', Social Studies of Science, 11 (1): 310.
Dagognet, Francois (1913) Ecriture et Iconographie,
Paris: Vrin.
Eisenstein, Elizabeth (1979) The Printing Press
as an Agen t of Change, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Farley, John and Geison, Gerald (1974) 'Science,
Politics and Spontaneous Generation in 19th Century France: The PasteurPouchet
Debate',Bulletin of the History of Medicine, 48 (2): 16198.
Geison, Gerald (1974) 'Pasteur', in C. Gillispie
(ed.), Dictionary of Scientific Biography, New York: Scribners.
Goody, Jack (1977) The Domestication of the Savage
Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Havelock, Eric A. (1981) Aux Origines de la Civilisation
Ecrite en Occident, Paris: Maspero.
Hunter, J. S. (1980) 'The National System of Scientific
Measurement', Science, 210: 86975.
KnorrCetina, K. D. (1981) The Manufacture
of Knowledge: An Essay on the Constructivist and Contextual Nature of Science,
Oxford: Pergamon Press.
KnorrCetina, K. D. and Cicourel, A. (eds)
(1981) Advances in Social Theory: Toward an Integration of Micro
and MacroSociologies, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Latour, Bruno (1981a) 'Qu'estce qu'être
Pastorien?' (in preparation).
Latour, Bruno (1981b) Irréductions: Tractatus ScientificoPoliticus, Paris: Chezloteur.
Latour, Bruno and Fabbri, Paolo (1977) 'Pouvoir et
Devoir dans un Article de Sciences Exactes', Actes de la Recherche,
13: 8295.
Latour, Bruno and Woolgar, Steve (1979) Laboratory
Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts, London and Beverly
HiHs: Sage.
Leonard, Jacques (1977) La Vie Quotidienne des
Medecins de L'Ouest au 19_ Siecle, Paris: Hachette.
Lynch, Michael (1982) Art and Artefact in Laboratory
Science: A Study of Shop Work and Shop Talk in a Research Laboratory, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
McNeil, John, (1976) Plagues and People, New
York: Doubleday.
Nelkin, Dorothy (ed.) (1979) Controversy, Politics
of Technical Decisions, London and Beverly HiHs: Sage.
Pasteur, Louis (1871) Quelques Reflexions sur
le Science en France, Paris.
Rosenkranz, Barbara (1972) Public Health in the
State of Massachusetts l8421936, Changing Views, Harvard: Harvard
University Press.
SalomonBayet, Claire (1982) 'La Pasteurisation
de la Médecine Française' (in preparation).
Serres, Michel (1974) Hermés III, La Traduction,
Paris: Editions de Minuit.
Serres, Michel (1980) Le Parasite, Paris:
Grasset.
Woolgar, Steve (1981) 'Interests and Explanation
in the Social Study of Science', Social Studies of Science, 11 (3):
36594.